The Project Gutenberg EBook of Plato's Doctrine respecting the rotation of the Earth and Aristotle's Comment upon that Doctrine, by George Grote This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org Title: Plato's Doctrine respecting the rotation of the Earth and Aristotle's Comment upon that Doctrine Author: George Grote Release Date: August 7, 2012 [EBook #40439] Language: English Character set encoding: ASCII *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK PLATO'S DOCTRINE--ROTATION OF EARTH *** Produced by Ed Brandon as part of the on-line Grote Project PLATO'S DOCTRINE RESPECTING THE ROTATION OF THE EARTH, AND ARISTOTLE'S COMMENT UPON THAT DOCTRINE. BY GEORGE GROTE, ESQ. LONDON: JOHN MURRAY, ALBEMARLE STREET. 1860. _The right of Translation is reserved._ LONDON: PRINTED BY WILLIAM CLOWES AND SONS, STAMFORD STREET, AND CHARING CROSS. EXAMINATION OF THE THREE FOLLOWING QUESTIONS:-- 1. WHETHER THE DOCTRINE OF THE EARTH'S ROTATION IS AFFIRMED OR IMPLIED IN THE PLATONIC TIMAEUS? 2. IF AFFIRMED OR IMPLIED, IN WHAT SENSE? 3. WHAT IS THE COSMICAL FUNCTION WHICH PLATO ASSIGNS TO THE EARTH IN THE TIMAEUS? PREFACE. The following paper was originally intended as an explanatory note on the Platonic Timaeus, in the work which I am now preparing on Plato and Aristotle. Interpreting, differently from others, the much debated passage in which Plato describes the cosmical function of the Earth, I found it indispensable to give my reasons for this new view. But I soon discovered that those reasons could not be comprised within the limits of a note. Accordingly I here publish them in a separate Dissertation. The manner in which the Earth's rotation was conceived, illustrates the scientific character of the Platonic and Aristotelian age, as contrasted with the subsequent development and improvement of astronomy. PLATO--ON THE EARTH'S ROTATION. In Plato, Timaeus, p. 40 B, we read the following words--[Greek: Ge=n de\ tropho\n me\n e(mete/ran, ei(llome/nen de\ peri\ to\n dia\ panto\s po/lon tetame/non phu/laka kai\ demiourgo\n nukto/s te kai\ e(me/ras e)mechane/sato, pro/ten kai\ presbuta/ten theo=n, o(/soi e)nto\s ou)ra/nou gego/nasi.] I give the text as it stands in Stallbaum's edition. The obscurity of this passage is amply attested by the numerous differences of opinion to which it has given rise, both in ancient and in modern times. Various contemporaries of Plato ([Greek: e)/nioi]--Aristot. De Coelo, II. 13, p. 293 b. 30) understood it as asserting or implying the rotatory movement of the earth in the centre of the Kosmos, and adhered to this doctrine as their own. Aristotle himself alludes to these contemporaries without naming them, and adopts their interpretation of the passage; but dissents from the doctrine, and proceeds to impugn it by arguments. Cicero mentions (Academic II. 39) that there were persons who believed Plato to have indicated the same doctrine obscurely, in his Timaeus: this passage must undoubtedly be meant. Plutarch devotes a critical chapter to the enquiry, what was Plato's real doctrine as to the cosmical function of the earth--its movement or rest (Quaestion. Platonic. VII. 3, p. 1006.) There exists a treatise, in Doric dialect, entitled [Greek: Ti/maio** to= Lo/kro Peri\ Psucha=s Ko/smo kai\ Phu/sios], which is usually published along with the works of Plato. This treatise was supposed in ancient times to be a genuine production of the Lokrian Timaeus, whom Plato introduces as his spokesman in the dialogue so called. As such, it was considered to be of much authority in settling questions of interpretation as to the Platonic Timaeus. But modern critics hold, I believe unanimously, that it is the work of some later Pythagorean or Platonist, excerpted or copied from the Platonic Timaeus. This treatise represents the earth as being in the centre and at rest. But its language, besides being dark and metaphorical, departs widely from the phraseology of the Platonic Timaeus: especially in this--that it makes no mention of the cosmical axis, nor of the word [Greek: i)llome/nen] or [Greek: ei(loume/nen]. Alexander of Aphrodisias (as we learn from Simplikius ad Aristot. De Coelo, fol. 126) followed the construction of Plato given by Aristotle. "It was improbable (he said) that Aristotle could be ignorant either what the word signified, or what was Plato's purpose" ([Greek: a)lla\ to=| A)ristote/lei, phesi\n, ou(/to le/gonti _i)/llesthai_, ou)k eu)/logon a)ntile/gein; o(s a)letho=s ga\r ou)/te te=s le/xeos to\ semaino/menon ei)ko\s e)=n a)gnoei=n au)to\n, ou)/te to\n Pla/tonos skopo/n.] This passage is not given in the Scholia of Brandis). Alexander therefore construed [Greek: i)llome/nen] as meaning or implying rotatory movement, though in so doing he perverted (so Simplikius says) the true meaning to make it consonant with his own suppositions. Proklus maintains that Aristotle has interpreted the passage erroneously,--that [Greek: i)llome/nen] is equivalent to [Greek: sphiggome/nen] or [Greek: xunechome/nen]--and that Plato intends by it to affirm the earth as at rest in the centre of the Kosmos (ad Timaeum, Book iv., p. 681 ed. Schneider). Simplikius himself is greatly perplexed, and scarcely ventures to give a positive opinion of his own. On the whole, he inclines to believe that [Greek: i)llome/nen] might possibly be understood, by superficial readers, so as to signify rotation, though such is not its proper and natural sense: that some Platonists did so misunderstand it: and that Aristotle accepted their sense for the sake of the argument, without intending himself to countenance it (ad Aristot. De Coelo, p. 126). Both Proklus and Simplikius, we must recollect, believed in the genuineness of the Doric treatise ascribed to Timaeus Locrus. Reasoning upon this basis, they of course saw, that if Aristotle had correctly interpreted Plato, Plato himself must have interpreted _incorrectly_ the doctrine of Timaeus. They had to ascribe wrong construction either to Plato or to Aristotle: and they could not bear to ascribe it to Plato. Alkinous, in his Eisagoge (c. 15) gives the same interpretation as Proklus. But it is remarkable that in his paraphrase of the Platonic words, he calls the earth [Greek: e(me/ras phu/lax kai\ nukto/s]: omitting the significant epithet [Greek: demiourgo/s]. In regard to modern comments upon the same disputed point, I need only mention (besides those of M. Cousin, in the notes upon his translation of the 'Timaeus', and of Martin in his 'Etudes sur le Timee') the elaborate discussion which it has received in the two recent Dissertations 'Ueber die kosmischen Systeme der Griechen,' by Gruppe and Boeckh. Gruppe has endeavoured, upon the evidence of this passage, supported by other collateral proofs, to show that Plato, towards the close of his life, arrived at a belief, first, in the rotation of the earth round its own axis, next, at the double movement of the earth, both rotation and translation, round the sun as a centre (that is, the heliocentric or Copernican system): that Plato was the first to make this discovery, but that he was compelled to announce it in terms intentionally equivocal and obscure, for fear of offending the religious sentiments of his contemporaries ('Die kosmischen Systeme der Griechen, von O. F. Gruppe,' Berlin, 1851). To this dissertation M. Boeckh--the oldest as well as the ablest of all living philologists--has composed an elaborate reply, with his usual fulness of illustrative matter and sobriety of inference. Opinions previously delivered by him (in his early treatises on the Platonic and Pythagoreian philosophy) had been called in question by Gruppe: he has now re-asserted them and defended them at length, maintaining that Plato always held the earth to be stationary and the sidereal sphere rotatory--and answering or extenuating the arguments which point to an opposite conclusion ('Untersuchungen ueber das kosmische System des Platon, von August Boeckh,' Berlin, 1852). Gruppe has failed in his purpose of proving that Plato adopted either of the two above-mentioned doctrines--either the rotation of the earth round its own axis, or the translation of the earth round the sun as a centre. On both these points I concur with Boeckh in the negative view. But though I go along with his reply as to its negative results, I cannot think it satisfactory in its positive aspect as an exposition of the doctrine proclaimed in the Platonic Timaeus: nor can I admit that the main argument of M. Boeckh's treatise is sufficient to support the inference which he rests upon it. Moreover, he appears to me to set aside or explain away too lightly the authority of Aristotle. I agree with Alexander of Aphrodisias and with Gruppe who follows him, in pronouncing Aristotle to be a good witness, when he declares what were the doctrines proclaimed in the Platonic Timaeus; though I think that Gruppe has not accurately interpreted either Timaeus or Aristotle. The capital argument of Boeckh is as follows: "The Platonic Timaeus affirms, in express and unequivocal terms, the rotation of the outer celestial sphere (the sidereal sphere or Aplanes) in twenty-four hours, as bringing about and determining the succession of day and night. Whoever believes this cannot at the same time believe that the earth revolves round its own axis in twenty-four hours, and that the succession of day and night is determined thereby. The one of these two affirmations excludes the other; and, as the first of the two is proclaimed, beyond all possibility of doubt, in the Platonic Timaeus, so we may be sure that the second of the two cannot be proclaimed in that same discourse. If any passage therein seems to countenance it, we must look for some other mode of interpreting the passage." This is the main argument of M. Boeckh, and also of Messrs. Cousin and Martin. The latter protests against the idea of imputing to Plato "un melange monstrueux de deux systemes incompatibles" (Etudes sur le Timee, vol. ii. p. 86-88). As applied to any person educated in the modern astronomy, the argument is irresistible. But is it equally irresistible when applied to Plato and to Plato's time? I think not. The incompatibility which appears so glaring at present, did not suggest itself to him or to his contemporaries. To prove this we have only to look at the reasoning of Aristotle, who (in the treatise De Coelo, ii. 13-14, p. 293. b. 30, 296. a. 25) notices and controverts the doctrine of the rotation of the earth, with express reference to the followers of the Platonic Timaeus--and who (if we follow the view of Martin) imputes this doctrine with wilful falsehood to Plato, for the purpose of contemptuously refuting it "pour se donner le plaisir de la refuter avec dedain." Granting the view of M. Boeckh (still more that of Martin) to be correct, we should find Aristotle arguing thus:--"Plato affirms the diurnal rotation of the earth round the centre of the cosmical axis. This is both incredible, and incompatible with his own distinct affirmation that the sidereal sphere revolves in twenty-four hours. It is a glaring inconsistency that the same author should affirm both the one and the other." Such would have been Aristotle's reasoning, on the hypothesis which I am considering; but when we turn to his treatise we find that he does not employ this argument at all. He contests the alleged rotation of the earth upon totally different arguments--chiefly on the ground that rotatory motion is not natural to the earth, that the kind of motion natural to the earth is rectilineal, towards the centre; and he adds various corollaries flowing from this doctrine which I shall not now consider. At the close of his refutation, he states in general terms that the celestial appearances, as observed by scientific men, coincided with his doctrine. Hence we may plainly see that Aristotle probably did not see the incompatibility, supposed to be so glaring, upon which M. Boeckh's argument is founded. To say the least, even if he saw it, he did not consider it as glaring and decisive. He would have put it in the foreground of his refutation, if he had detected the gross contradiction upon which M. Boeckh insists. But Aristotle does not stand alone in this dulness of vision. Among the various commentators, ancient and modern, who follow him, discussing the question now before us, not one takes notice of M. Boeckh's argument. He himself certifies to us this fact, claiming the argument as his own, and expressing his astonishment that all the previous critics had passed it over, though employing other reasons much weaker to prove the same point. We read in M. Boeckh's second 'Commentatio de Platonico Systemate Coelestium Globorum et de Vera Indole Astronomiae Philolaicae,' Heidelberg, 1810, p. 9, the following words:-- "Non moveri tellurem, Proclus et Simplicius ostendunt ex Phaedone. Parum firmum tamen argumentum est ex Phaedone ductum ad interpretandum Timaei locum: nec melius alterum, quod Locrus Timaeus, quem Plato sequi putabatur, terram stare affirmat: quia, ut nuper explicuimus, non Plato ex Locro, sed personatus Locrus ex Platone, sua compilavit. At omnium firmissionum et certissimum argumentum ex ipso nostro dialogo sumptum, _adhuc, quod jure mirere, nemo reperit_. Etenim, quum, paulo supra, orbem stellarum fixarum, quem Graeci [Greek: a)plane=] appellant, dextrorsum ferri quotidiano motu Plato statuebat, non poterat ullum terrae motum admittere; quia, _qui hunc admittit, illum non tollere non potest_." (This passage appears again cited by M. Boeckh himself in his more recent dissertation 'Untersuchungen ueber das kosmische System des Platon,' p. 11). The writers named (p. 7) as having discussed the question, omitting or disregarding this most cogent argument, are names extending from Aristotle down to Ruhnken and Ideler. It is honourable to the penetration of M. Boeckh that he should have pointed out, what so many previous critics had overlooked, that these two opinions are scientifically incompatible. He wonders, and there may be good ground for wondering, how it happened that none of these previous writers were aware of the incompatibility. But the fact that it did not occur to them, is not the less certain, and is of the greatest moment in reference to the question now under debate; for we are not now inquiring what is or is not scientifically true or consistent, but what were the opinions of Plato. M. Boeckh has called our attention to the fact, that these two opinions are incompatible; but can we safely assume that Plato must have perceived such incompatibility between them? Surely not. The Pythagoreans of his day did not perceive it; their cosmical system included both the revolution of the earth and the revolution of the sidereal sphere round the central fire, ten revolving bodies in all (Aristotel. Metaphysic. i. 35, p. 96 a. 10. De Coelo, ii. 13, p. 293 b. 21). They were not aware that the revolutions of the one annulled those of the other as to effect, and that their system thus involved the two contradictory articles, or "melange monstrueux," of which Martin speaks so disdainfully. Nay, more, their opponent, Aristotle, while producing other arguments against them, never points out the contradiction. Since it did not occur to them, we can have no greater difficulty in believing that neither did it occur to Plato. Indeed, the wonder would rather be if Plato _had_ seen an astronomical incompatibility which escaped the notice both of Aristotle and of many subsequent writers who wrote at a time when astronomical theories had been developed and compared with greater fulness. Even Ideler, a good astronomer as well as a good scholar, though he must surely have known that Plato asserted the rotation of the sidereal sphere (for no man can read the 'Timaeus' without knowing it), ascribed to him also the other doctrine inconsistent with it, not noticing such inconsistency until M. Boeckh pointed it out. It appears to me, therefore, that M. Boeckh has not satisfactorily made good his point--"Plato cannot have believed in the diurnal rotation of the earth, because he unquestionably believed in the rotation of the sidereal sphere as causing the succession of night and day." For, though the two doctrines really are incompatible, yet the critics antecedent to M. Boeckh took no notice of such incompatibility. We cannot presume that Plato saw what Aristotle and other authors, even many writing under a more highly developed astronomy, did not see. We ought rather, I think, to presume the contrary, unless Plato's words distinctly attest that he did see farther than his successors. Now let us examine what Plato's words do attest:--[Greek: ge=n de\ tropho\n me\n e(mete/ran, ei(llome/nen] (al. [Greek: ei(lome/nen, i)llome/nen]) [Greek: de\ peri\ to\n dia\ panto\s po/lon tetame/non phu/laka kai\ demiourgo\n nukto/s te kai\ e(me/ras e)mechane/sato, pro/ten kai\ presbuta/ten theo=n, o(/soi e)nto\s ou)ra/nou gego/nasi.] I explain these words as follows:-- In the passage immediately preceding, Plato had described the uniform and unchanging rotation of the outer sidereal sphere, or Circle of The Same, and the erratic movements of the sun, moon, and planets, in the interior Circles of the Diverse. He now explains the situation and functions of the earth. Being the first and most venerable of the intra-kosmic deities, the earth has the most important place in the interior of the kosmos--the centre. It is packed, fastened, or rolled, close round the axis which traverses the entire kosmos; and its function is to watch over and bring about the succession of night and day. _Plato conceives the kosmic axis itself as a solid cylinder revolving or turning round, and causing thereby the revolution of the circumference or the sidereal sphere._ The outer circumference of the kosmos not only revolves round its axis, but obeys a rotatory impulse emanating from its axis, like the spinning of a teetotum or the turning of a spindle. Plato in the Republic illustrates the cosmical axis by comparison with a spindle turned by Necessity, and describes it as causing by its own rotation the rotation of all the heavenly bodies (Republ. x. p. 616, c. 617 A). [Greek: e)k de\ to=n a)/kron tetame/non A)na/gkes a)/trakton, di' ou(= pa/sas e)pistre/phesthai ta\s peri/phoras . . . , kuklei=sthai de\ de\ strepho/menon to\n a)/trakton o(/lon me\n te\n au)te\n phoran . . . . stre/phesthai de\ au)to\n e)n toi=s A)na/gkes go/nasin.][1] [Footnote 1: Proklus in his Commentary on the Platonic Timaeus (p. 682, Schn.) notes this passage of the Republic as the proper comparison from which to interpret how Plato conceived the cosmical axis. In many points he explains this correctly; but he omits to remark that the axis is expressly described as revolving, and as causing the revolution of the peripheral substance:-- ----[Greek: to\n de\ a)/xona mi/an theo/teta sunagogo\n me\n to=n ke/ntron tou= panto\s sunektike\n de\ tou= o(/lou ko/smou, _kinetike\n de\ to=n thei/on periphoro=n_, peri\ e(\n e( chorei/a** to=n o(/lon, peri\ e(\n ai( a)nakukle/seis, a)ne/chousan to\n o(/lon ou)rano\n,** e(\n kai\ A)/tlanta dia\ tou=to proseire/kasin, o(s a)/trepton kai\ a)/truton e)ne/rgeian e)/chousan. kai\ me/ntoi kai\ to\ tetame/non** e)ndei/knutai** tite/nion ei)=nai te\n mi/an _tau/ten du/namin, te\n phrouretike\n te=s a)nakukle/seos to=n o(/lon_.] Here Proklus recognises the efficacy of the axis in producing and maintaining the revolution of the Kosmos, but he does not remark that it initiates this movement by revolving itself. The [Greek: Theote\s], which Proklus ascribes to the axis, is invested in the earth packed round it, by the Platonic Timaeus.] Now the function which Plato ascribes to the earth in the passage of the Timaeus before us is very analogous to that which in the Republic he ascribes to Necessity--the active guardianship of the axis of the kosmos and the maintenance of its regular rotation. With a view to the exercise of this function, the earth is planted in the centre of the axis, the very root of the kosmic soul (Plato, Timaeus, p. 34 B). It is even "packed close round the axis," in order to make sure that the axis shall not be displaced from its proper situation and direction. The earth is thus not merely active and influential, but is really the chief regulator of the march of the kosmos, being the immediate neighbour and auxiliary of the kosmic soul. Such a function is worthy of "the first and eldest of intra-kosmic deities," as Plato calls the earth. With perfect propriety he may say that the earth, in the exercise of such a function, "is guardian and artificer of day and night." This is noway inconsistent with that which he says in another passage, that the revolutions of the outer sidereal sphere determine day and night. For these revolutions of the outer sidereal sphere depend upon the revolutions of the axis, which latter is kept in uniform position and movement by the earth grasping it round its centre and revolving with it. The earth does not determine days and nights by means of its own rotations, but by its continued influence upon the rotations of the kosmic axis, and (through this latter) upon those of the outer sidereal sphere. It is important to attend to the circumstance last mentioned, and to understand in what sense Plato admitted a rotatory movement of the earth. In my judgment, the conception respecting the earth and its functions, as developed in the Platonic Timaeus, has not been considered with all its points taken together. One point among several, and that too the least important point, has been discussed as if it were the whole, because it falls in with the discussions of subsequent astronomy. Thus Plato admits the rotation of the earth, but he does not admit it as producing any effects, or as the primary function of the earth: it is only an indirect consequence of the position which the earth occupies in the discharge of its primary function--of keeping the cosmical axis steady, and maintaining the uniformity of its rotations. If the cosmical axis is to revolve, the earth, being closely packed and fastened round it, must revolve along with it. If the earth stood still, and resisted all rotation of its own, it would at the same time arrest the rotations of the cosmical axis, and of course those of the entire kosmos besides. The above is the interpretation which I propose of the passage in the Platonic Timaeus, and which I shall show to coincide with Aristotle's comment upon it. Messrs. Boeckh and Martin interpret differently. They do not advert to the sense in which Plato conceives the axis of the kosmos--not as an imaginary line, but as a solid revolving cylinder; and moreover they understand the function assigned by the Platonic Timaeus to the earth in a way which I cannot admit. They suppose that the function assigned to the earth is not to keep up and regularize, but to withstand and countervail, the rotation of the kosmos. M. Boeckh comments upon Gruppe, who had said (after Ideler) that when the earth is called [Greek: phu/laka _kai\ demiourgo\n_ nukto\s kai\ e(me/ras], Plato must have meant to designate some active function ascribed to it, and not any function merely passive or negative. I agree with Gruppe in this remark, and I have endeavoured to point out what this active function of the earth is, in the Platonic theory. But M. Boeckh (Untersuchungen, &c., p. 69-70) controverts Gruppe's remark, observing, first, that it is enough if the earth is in any way necessary to the production of the given effect; secondly, that if active force be required, the earth (in the Platonic theory) does exercise such, by its purely passive resistance, which is in itself an energetic putting forth of power. M. Boeckh's words are:--"Es kommt nur darauf an, dass er ein Werk, eine Wirkung, hervorbringt oder zu einer Wirkung beitraegt, die ohne ihn nicht waere: dann ist er durch seine Wirksamkeit ein Werkmeister der Sache, sey es auch ohne active Thaetigkeit, durch bloss passiven Widerstand, der auch eine maechtige Kraft-aeusserung ist. Die Erde ist Werkmeisterin der Nacht und des Tages, wie Martin (b. ii. p. 88) sehr treffend sagt 'par son energique existence, c'est a dire, par son immobilite meme:' denn sie setzt der taeglichen Bewegung des Himmels bestaendig eine gleiche Kraft in entgegengesetzter Richtung entgegen. So _muss_ nach dem Zusammenhange ausgelegt werden: so meint es Platon klar und ohne Verhuellungen: denn wenige Zeilen vorher hat er gesagt, Nacht und Tag, das heisst ein Sterntag oder Zeittag, sei ein Umlauf des Kreises des Selbigen--_das ist, eine taegliche Umkreisung des Himmels von Osten nach Westen, wodurch also die Erde in Stillstand versetzt ist:_ und diese taegliche Bewegung des Himmels hat er im vorhergehenden immer und immer gelehrt." . . . . "Indem Platon die Erde nennt [Greek: ei(lome/nen], nicht [Greek: peri\ to\n e(aute=s po/lon], sondern [Greek: peri\ to\n dia\ panto\s po/lon tetame/non], setzt er also die taegliche Bewegung des Himmels voraus" (p. 70-71).[2] [Footnote 2: "We are only required to show, that the Earth produces a work or an effect,--or contributes to an effect which would not exist without such help: the Earth is then, through such operation, an _Artificer_ of what is produced, even without any positive activity, by its simply passive resistance, which indeed is in itself a powerful exercise of force.** The Earth is Artificer of night and day, according to the striking expression of Martin, 'par son energique existence, c'est-a-dire, par son immobilite meme:' for the Earth opposes, to the diurnal movement of the Heavens, a constant and equal force in the opposite direction. This explanation _must_ be the true one required by the context: this is Plato's meaning, plainly and without disguise: for he has said, a few lines before, that Night and Day (that is, a sidereal day, or day of time) is a diurnal revolution of the Heaven from East to West, whereby accordingly the Earth is assumed as at rest: And this diurnal movement of the Heaven he has taught over and over again in the preceding part of his discourse."--"Since therefore Plato calls the Earth [Greek: ei(lome/nen], not [Greek: peri\ to\n e(aute=s po/lon], but [Greek: peri\ to\n dia\ panto\s po/lon tetame/non], he implies thereby the diurnal movement of the Heaven."] I not only admit but put it in the front of my own case, that Plato in the Timaeus assumes the diurnal movement of the celestial sphere; but I contend that he also assumes the diurnal rotation of the earth. M. Boeckh founds his contrary interpretation upon the unquestionable truth that these two assumptions are inconsistent; and upon the inference that because the two cannot stand together in fact, therefore they cannot have stood together in the mind of Plato. In that inference I have already stated that I cannot acquiesce. But while M. Boeckh takes so much pains to vindicate Plato from one contradiction, he unconsciously involves Plato in another contradiction, for which, in my judgment, there is no foundation whatever. M. Boeckh affirms that the function of the earth (in the Platonic Timaeus) is to put forth a great force of passive resistance--"to oppose constantly, against the diurnal movement of the heavens, an equal force in an opposite direction." Is it not plain, upon this supposition, that the kosmos would come to a standstill, and that its rotation would cease altogether? As the earth is packed close or fastened round the cosmical axis, so, if the axis endeavours to revolve with a given force, and the earth resists with equal force, the effect will be that the two forces will destroy one another, and that neither the earth nor the axis will move at all. There would be the same nullifying antagonism as if,--reverting to the analogous case of the spindle and the verticilli (already alluded to) in the tenth book of the Republic,--as if, while Ananke turned the spindle with a given force in one direction, Klotho (instead of lending assistance) were to apply her hand to the outermost verticillus with equal force of resistance in the opposite direction (see Reipubl. x. p. 617 D). It is plain that the spindle would never turn at all. Here, then, is a grave contradiction attaching to the view of Boeckh and Martin as to the function of the earth. They have not, in my judgment, sufficiently investigated the manner in which Plato represents to himself the cosmical axis: nor have they fully appreciated what is affirmed or implied in the debated word [Greek: ei(lo/menon--ei(lou/menon--i)llo/menon]. That word has been explained partly by Ruhnken in his notes on Timaei Lexicon, but still more by Buttmann in his Lexilogus, so accurately and copiously as to leave nothing further wanting. I accept fully the explanation given by Buttmann, and have followed it throughout this article. After going over many other examples, Buttmann comes to consider this passage of the Platonic Timaeus; and he explains the word [Greek: ei(lome/nen] or [Greek: i)llo/menen] as meaning--"_sich draengen oder gedraengt werden_ um die Axe: d. h. von allen Seiten her an die Axe. Auch lasse man sich das Praesens nicht irren: die Kraefte, welche den Weltbau machen und zusammen halten, sind als fortdauernd thaetig gedacht. Die Erde draengt sich (ununterbrochen) an den Pol, _macht, bildet eine Kugel um ihn_. Welcher Gebrauch voellig entspricht dem wonach dasselbe Verbum ein _einwickeln_, _einhuellen_, bedeutet. Auch hier mengt sich in der Vorstellung einiges hinzu, was auf ein _biegen_ _winden_, und mitunter auf ein _drehen_ fuehrt: was aber _ueberall nur ein durch die Sache selbst hinzutretender Begriff ist_," p. 151. And again, p. 154, he gives the result--that the word has only "die Bedeutung _draengen_, _befestigen_, nebst den davon ausgehenden--die von _drehen_, _winden_, aber ihm _gaenzlich fremd_ sind, _und nur aus der Natur der Gegenstaende in einigen Faellen als Nebengedanken hinzutreten_."[3] [Footnote 3: "To _pack itself_, or to _be packed_, round the axis: that is, upon the axis from all sides. We must not be misled by the present tense: for the forces, which compose and hold together the structure of the universe, are conceived as continuously in active operation. The Earth _packs itself_, or _is packed_, on to the axis--_makes or forms a ball round the axis:_ which corresponds fully to that other usage of the word, in the sense of _wrapping up_ or _swathing round_. Here too there is a superadded something blended with the idea, which conducts us to _turning_, _winding_, and thus to _revolving_: but this is every where nothing more than an accessory notion, suggested by the circumstances of the case. The word has only the meaning, to _pack_, to _fasten_--the senses, to _wind_, to _revolve_, are altogether foreign to it, and can only be superadded as accessory ideas, in certain particular instances, by the special nature of the case."] In these last words Buttmann has exactly distinguished the true, constant, and essential meaning of the word, from the casual accessories which become conjoined with it by the special circumstances of some peculiar cases. The constant and true meaning of the word is, _being packed or fastened close round_, _squeezing or grasping around_. The idea of _rotating_ or _revolving_ is quite foreign to this meaning, but may nevertheless become conjoined with it, in certain particular cases, by accidental circumstances. Let us illustrate this. When I say that a body _A_ is [Greek: ei(lo/menon] or [Greek: i)llo/menon] (packed or fastened close round, squeezing or grasping around), another body _B_, I affirm nothing about revolution or rotation. This is an idea foreign to the proposition _per se_, yet capable of being annexed or implicated with it under some accidental circumstances. Whether in any particular case it be so implicated or not depends on the question "What is the nature of the body _B_, round which I affirm _A_ to be fastened?" 1. It may be an oak tree or a pillar, firmly planted and stationary. 2. It may be some other body, moving, but moving in a rectilinear direction. 3. Lastly, it may be a body rotating or intended to rotate, like a spindle, a spit, or the rolling cylinder of a machine. In the first supposition, all motion is excluded: in the second, rectilinear motion is implied, but rotatory motion is excluded: in the third, rotatory motion is implied as a certain adjunct. The body which is fastened round another, must share the motion or the rest of that other. If the body _B_ is a revolving cylinder, and if I affirm that _A_ is packed or fastened close round it, I introduce the idea of rotation; though only as an accessory and implied fact, in addition to that which the proposition affirms. The body _A_, being fastened round the cylinder _B_, must either revolve along with it and round it, or it must arrest the rotation of _B_. If the one revolves, so must the other; both must either revolve together, or stand still together. This is a new fact, distinct from what is affirmed in the proposition, yet implied in it or capable of being inferred from it through induction and experience. Here we see exactly the position of Plato in regard to the rotation of the earth. He does not affirm it in express terms, but he affirms what implies it. For when he says that the earth is packed, or fastened close round the cosmical axis, he conveys to us by implication the knowledge of another and distinct fact--that the earth and the cosmical axis must either revolve together or remain stationary together--that the earth must either revolve along with the axis or arrest the revolutions of the axis. It is manifest that Plato does not mean the revolutions of the axis of the kosmos to be arrested: they are absolutely essential to the scheme of the Timaeus--they are the grand motive-agency of the kosmos. He must, therefore, mean to imply that the earth revolves along with and around the cosmical axis. And thus the word [Greek: ei(lo/menon] or [Greek: i)llo/menon], according to Buttmann's doctrine, becomes accidentally conjoined, through the specialities of this case, with an accessory idea of rotation or revolution; though that idea is foreign to its constant and natural meaning. Now if we turn to Aristotle, we shall find that he understood the word [Greek: ei(lo/menon] or [Greek: i)llo/menon], and the proposition of Plato, exactly in this sense. Here I am compelled to depart from Buttmann, who affirms (p. 152), with an expression of astonishment, that Aristotle misunderstood the proposition of Plato, and interpreted [Greek: ei(lo/menon] or [Greek: i)llo/menon] as if it meant directly as well as incontestably, _rotating_ or _revolving_. Proklus, in his Commentary on the Timaeus, had before raised the same controversy with Aristotle--[Greek: i)llome/nen de\, te\n sphiggome/nen deloi= kai\ sunechome/nen ou) ga\r o(s A)ristote/les oi)/etai, te\n kinoume/nen] (Procl. p. 681). Let us, therefore, examine the passages of Aristotle out of which this difficulty arises. The passages are two, both of them in the second book De Coelo; one in cap. 13, the other in cap. 14 (p. 293 b. 30, 296 a. 25). 1. The first stands--[Greek: e)/nioi de\ kai\ keime/nen (te\n ge=n) e)pi\ tou= ke/ntrou phasi\n au)te\n i)/llesthai peri\ to\n dia\ panto\s tetame/non po/lon, o(/sper e)n to=| Timai/o|** ge/graptai.** Such is the reading of Bekker in the Berlin edition: but he gives various readings of two different MSS.--the one having [Greek: i)/llesthai kai\ kinei=sthai]--the other ei(lei=sthai** kai\ kinei=sthai]. 2. The second stands, beginning chap. 14--[Greek: e(mei=s de\ le/gomen pro=ton po/teron] (the earth) [Greek: e)/chei ki/nesin e)\ me/nei; katha/per ga\r ei)/pomen, oi( me\n au)te\n e(\n to=n a)/stron poiou=sin, oi( d' e)pi\** tou= me/sou the/ntes i)/llesthai kai\ kinei=shai/ phasi peri\ to\n po/lon me/son.] Now, in the first of these two passages, where Aristotle simply brings the doctrine to view without any comment, he expressly refers to the Timaeus, and therefore quotes the expression of that dialogue without any enlargement. He undoubtedly understands the affirmation of Plato--that the earth was fastened round the cosmical axis--as implying that it rotated along with the rotations of that axis. Aristotle thus construes [Greek: i)/llesthai], _in that particular proposition_ of the Timaeus, as implying rotation. But he plainly did not construe [Greek: i)/llesthai] as naturally and constantly either denoting or implying rotation. This is proved by his language in the second passage, where he reproduces the very same doctrine with a view to discuss and confute it, and without special reference to the Platonic Timaeus. Here we find that he is not satisfied to express the doctrine by the single word [Greek: i)/llesthai]. He subjoins another verb--[Greek: i)/llesthai kai\ kinei=sthai]: thus bringing into explicit enunciation the fact of rotatory movement, which, while [Greek: i)/llesthai] stood alone, was only known by implication and inference from the circumstances of the particular case. If he had supposed [Greek: i)/llesthai] by itself to signify _revolving_ the addition of [Greek: kinei=sthai] would have been useless, unmeaning, and even impertinent. Aristotle, as Boeckh remarks, is not given to multiply words unnecessarily. It thus appears, when we examine the passages of Aristotle, that he understood [Greek: i)/llesthai] quite in conformity with Buttmann's explanation. Rotatory movement forms no part of the meaning of the word; yet it may accidentally, in a particular case, be implied as an adjunct of the meaning, by virtue of the special circumstances of that case. Aristotle describes the doctrine as held by _some persons_. He doubtless has in view various Platonists of his time, who adopted and defended what had been originally advanced by Plato in the Timaeus. M. Boeckh, in a discussion of some length (Untersuch. p. 76-84), maintains the opinion that the reading in the first passage of Aristotle is incorrect; that the two words [Greek: i)/llesthai kai\ kinei=sthai] ought to stand in the first as they do in the second,--as he thinks that they stood in the copy of Simplikius: that Aristotle only made reference to Plato with a view to the peculiar word [Greek: i)/llesthai], and not to the general doctrine of the rotation of the earth: that he comments upon this doctrine as held by others, but not by Plato--who (according to Boeckh) was known by everyone not to hold it. M. Boeckh gives this only as a conjecture, and I cannot regard his arguments in support of it as convincing. But even if he had convinced me that [Greek: i)/llesthai kai\ kinei=sthai] were the true reading in the first passage, as well as in the second, I should merely say that Aristotle had not thought himself precluded by the reference to the Timaeus from bringing out into explicit enunciation what the Platonists whom he had in view knew to be implied and intended by the passage. This indeed is a loose mode of citation, which I shall not ascribe to Aristotle without good evidence. In the present case such evidence appears to me wanting.[4] [Footnote 4: Exactness of citation is not always to be relied on among ancient commentators. Simplikius cites this very passage of the Timaeus with more than one inaccuracy.--(ad Aristot. De Coelo, fol. 125.)] M. Martin attributes to Aristotle something more than improper citation. He says (Etudes sur le Timee, vol. ii. p. 87), "Si Aristote citait l'opinion de la rotation de la terre comme un titre de gloire pour Platon, je dirais--il est probable que la verite l'y a force. Mais Aristote, qui admettait l'immobilite complete de la terre, attribue a Platon l'opinion contraire, _pour se donner le plaisir de la refuter avec dedain_." A few lines before, M. Martin had said that the arguments whereby Aristotle combated this opinion ascribed to Plato were "very feeble." I am at a loss to imagine in which of Aristotle's phrases M. Martin finds any trace of disdain or contempt, either for the doctrine or for those who held it. For my part, I find none. The arguments of Aristotle against the doctrine, whatever be their probative force, are delivered in that brief, calm, dry manner which is usual with him, without a word of sentiment or rhetoric, or anything [Greek: e)/xo tou= pra/gmatos]. Indeed, among all philosophers who have written much, I know none who is less open to the reproach of mingling personal sentiment with argumentative debate than Aristotle. Plato indulges frequently in irony, or sneering, or rhetorical invective; Aristotle very rarely. Moreover, even apart from the question of contempt, the part which M. Martin here assumes Aristotle to be playing, is among the strangest anomalies in the history of philosophy. Aristotle holds, and is anxious to demonstrate, the doctrine of the earth's immobility; he knows (so we are required to believe) that Plato not only holds the same doctrine, but has expressly affirmed it in the Timaeus: he might have produced Plato as an authority in his favour, and the passage of the Timaeus as an express declaration; yet he prefers to pervert, knowingly and deliberately, the meaning of this passage, and to cite Plato as a hostile instead of a friendly authority--simply "to give himself the pleasure of contemptuously refuting Plato's opinion!" But this is not all. M. Martin tells us that the arguments which Aristotle produces against the doctrine are, after all, very feeble. But he farther tells us that there was one argument which might have been produced, and which, if Aristotle had produced it, would have convicted Plato of "an enormous contradiction" (p. 88) in affirming that the earth revolved round the cosmical axis. Aristotle might have said to Plato--"You have affirmed, and you assume perpetually throughout the Timaeus, the diurnal revolution of the outer sidereal sphere; you now assert the diurnal revolution of the earth at the centre. Here is an enormous contradiction; the two cannot stand together."--Yet Aristotle, having this triumphant argument in his hands, says not a word about it, but contents himself with various other arguments which M. Martin pronounces to be very feeble. Perhaps M. Martin might say--"The contradiction exists; but Aristotle was not sharpsighted enough to perceive it; otherwise he would have advanced it." I am quite of this opinion. If Aristotle had perceived the contradiction, he would have brought it forward as the strongest point in his controversy. His silence is to me a proof that he did not perceive it. But this is a part of my case against M. Martin. I believe that Plato admitted both the two contradictory doctrines without perceiving the contradiction; and it is a strong presumption in favour of this view that Aristotle equally failed to perceive it--though in a case where, according to M. Martin, he did not scruple to resort to dishonest artifice. It appears to me that the difficulties and anomalies, in which we are involved from supposing that Aristotle either misunderstood or perverted the meaning of Plato--are far graver than those which would arise from admitting that Plato advanced a complicated theory involving two contradictory propositions, in the same dialogue, without perceiving the contradiction; more especially when the like failure of perception is indisputably ascribable to Aristotle--upon every view of the case. M. Cousin maintains the same interpretation of the Platonic passage as Boeckh and Martin, and defends it by a note on his translation of the Timaeus (p. 339). The five arguments which he produces are considered both by himself and by Martin to be unanswerable. As he puts them with great neatness and terseness, I here bestow upon them a separate examination. 1. "Platon a toujours ete considere dans l'antiquite comme partisan de l'immobilite absolue de la terre." M. Cousin had before said, "Aristote se fonde sur ce passage pour etablir que Platon a fait tourner la terre sur elle-meme: mais Aristote est, dans l'antiquite, le seul qui soutienne cette opinion." My reply is, that Aristotle is himself a portion and member of antiquity, and that the various Platonists, whom he undertakes to refute, are portions of it also. If M. Cousin appeals to the authority of antiquity, it must be to antiquity, not merely _minus_ Aristotle and these contemporary Platonists, but _against_ them. Now these are just the witnesses who had the best means of knowledge. Besides which, Aristotle himself, adopting and anxious to demonstrate the immobility of the earth, had every motive to cite Plato as a supporter, if Plato was such--and every motive to avoid citing Plato as an opponent, unless the truth of the case compelled him to do so. I must here add, that M. Cousin represents Aristotle as ascribing to Plato the doctrine that "la terre tourne sur elle-meme." This is not strictly exact. Aristotle understands the Platonic Timaeus as saying, "That the earth is packed and moved _round the axis of the kosmos_"--a different proposition. 2. "Dans plusieurs endroits de ses ouvrages ou Platon parle de l'equilibre de la terre, il ne dit pas un mot de sa rotation." I know of only _one_ such passage--Phaedon, p. 108--where undoubtedly Plato does not speak of the rotation of the earth; but neither does he speak of the rotation of the sidereal sphere and of the kosmos--nor of the axis of the kosmos. It is the figure and properties of the earth, considered in reference to mankind who inhabit it, that Plato sketches in the Phaedon; he takes little notice of its cosmical relations, and gives no general theory about the kosmos. M. Cousin has not adverted to the tenth Book of the Republic, where Plato does propound a cosmical theory, expressly symbolising the axis of the kosmos with its rotatory functions. 3. "Si la _terre suit le mouvement de l'axe du monde_, le mouvement de la huitieme sphere, qui est Le Meme, devient nul par rapport a elle, et les etoiles fixes, qui appartiennent a elle, demeurent en apparence dans une immobilite absolue: ce qui est contraire a _l'experience et au sens commun_, et a l'opinion de Platon, exprimee dans ce meme passage." This third argument of M. Cousin is the same as that which I have already examined in remarking upon M. Boeckh. The diurnal rotation of the earth cannot stand in the same astronomical system with the diurnal rotation of the sidereal sphere. Incontestably true (I have already said) as a point of science. But the question here is, not what opinions are scientifically consistent, but what opinions were held by Plato, and whether he detected the inconsistency between the two. I have shown grounds for believing that he did not--and not he alone, but many others along with him, Aristotle among the number. How, indeed, can this be denied, when we find M. Boeckh announcing that he is the _first_ among all the critics on the Timaeus, who has brought forward the inconsistency as a special ground for determining what Plato's opinion was--that no other critic before him had noticed it? The first words of this argument deserve particular attention, "Si la terre suit le mouvement de l'axe du monde." Here we have an exact recital of the doctrine proclaimed by the Platonic Timaeus, and ascribed to him by Aristotle (quite different from the doctrine "que la terre tourne sur elle-meme"). M. Cousin here speaks very distinctly about the cosmical axis, and about its movement; thus implying that Plato conceived it as a solid revolving cylinder. This, in my judgment, is the most essential point for clearing up the question in debate. The cosmical axis being of this character, when Plato affirms that the earth is _packed or fastened round it_ (_se roule_--Cousin: _se serre et s'enroule_--Martin: _draengt sich, macht eine Kugel um ihn_--Buttmann), I maintain that, in the plainest construction of the word, the earth does and must follow the movement of the axis--or arrest the movement of the axis. The word [Greek: ei(lome/nen] or [Greek: i)llome/nen] has no distinct meaning at all, if it does not mean this. The very synonyms ([Greek: sphiggome/nen, peridedeme/nen], &c.), which the commentators produce to prove that Plato describes the earth as at rest, do really prove that he describes it as rotating round and with the cosmical axis. We ought not to be driven from this plain meaning of the word, by the assurance of M. Cousin and others that Plato cannot have meant so, because it would involve him in an astronomical inconsistency. 4. "Les divers mouvemens des huit spheres expliquent toutes les apparences celestes; il n'y a donc aucune raison pour donner un mouvement a la terre." The terms of this fourth argument, if literally construed, would imply that Plato had devised a complete and satisfactory astronomical theory. I pass over this point, and construe them as M. Cousin probably intended: his argument will then stand thus--"The movement of the earth does not add anything to Plato's power of explaining astronomical appearances; therefore Plato had no motive to suggest a movement of the earth." I have already specified the sense in which I understand the Platonic Timaeus to affirm, or rather to imply, the rotation of the earth; and that sense is not open to the objections raised in M. Cousin's fourth and fifth arguments. The rotation of the earth, as it appears in the Platonic Timaeus, explains nothing, and is not intended to explain anything. It is a consequence, not a cause: it is a consequence arising from the position of the earth, as packed or fastened round the centre of the cosmical axis, whereby the earth participates, of necessity and as a matter of course, in the movements of that axis. The _function_ of the earth, thus planted in the centre of the kosmos, is to uphold and regulate the revolutions of the cosmical axis; and this function explains, in the scheme of the Platonic Timaeus, why the axis revolves uniformly and constantly without change or displacement. Now upon these revolutions of the cosmical axis all the revolutions of the exterior sphere depend. This is admitted by M. Cousin himself in argument 3. There is therefore every reason why Plato should assign such regulating function to the earth, the "first and oldest of intra-kosmic deities." The movement of the earth (as I before observed) is only an incidental consequence of the position necessary for the earth to occupy in performing such function. 5. "Enfin Platon assigne un mouvement aux etoiles fixes, et deux mouvemens aux planetes; puisqu'il ne range la terre ni avec les unes ni avec les autres, il y a lieu de croire qu'elle ne participe a aucun de leurs mouvemens." In so far as this argument is well-founded, it strengthens my case more than that of M. Cousin. The earth does not participate in the movements either of the fixed stars or of the planets; but it does participate in the revolutions of the cosmical axis, upon which these movements depend--the movements of the outer sphere, wholly and exclusively--the movements of the planets, to a very great degree, but not exclusively. The earth is not ranked either among the fixed stars or among the planets; it is a body or deity _sui generis_, having a special central function of its own, to regulate that cosmical axis which impels the whole system. The earth has a motion of its own, round and along with the cosmical axis to which it is attached; but this motion of the earth (I will again repeat, to prevent misapprehension) is a fact not important by itself, nor explaining anything. The grand and capital fact is the central position and regulating function of the earth, whereby all the cosmical motions, first those of the axis, next those of the exterior kosmos, are upheld and kept uniform. M. Cousin adds, as a sixth argument:-- "On peut ajouter a ces raisons que Platon aurait necessairement insiste sur le mouvement de la terre, s'il l'avait admis; et que ce point etoit trop controverse de son temps et trop important en lui-meme, pour qu'il ne fit que l'indiquer en se servant d'une expression equivoque." In the first place, granting Plato to have believed in the motion of the earth, can we also assume that he would necessarily have asserted it with distinctness and emphasis, as M. Cousin contends? I think not. Gruppe maintains exactly the contrary; telling us that Plato's language was intentionally obscure and equivocal--from fear of putting himself in open conflict with the pious and orthodox sentiment prevalent around him. I do not carry this part of the case so far as Gruppe, but I admit that it rests upon a foundation of reality. When we read (Plutarch, De Facie in Orbe Lunae, p. 923) how the motion of the earth, as affirmed by Aristarchus of Samos (doubtless in a far larger sense than Plato ever imagined, including both rotation and translation), was afterwards denounced as glaring impiety, we understand the atmosphere of religious opinion with which Plato was surrounded. And we also perceive that he might have reasons for preferring to indicate an astronomical heresy in terms suitable for philosophical hearers, rather than to proclaim it in such emphatic unequivocal words, as might be quoted by some future Meletus in case of an indictment before the Dikasts. We must remember that Plato had been actually present at the trial of Sokrates. He had heard the stress laid by the accusers on astronomical heresies, analogous to those of Anaxagoras, which they imputed to Sokrates--and the pains taken by the latter to deny that he held such opinions (see the Platonic Apology). The impression left by such a scene on Plato's mind was not likely to pass away: nor can we be surprised that he preferred to use propositions which involved and implied, rather than those which directly and undisguisedly asserted, the heretical doctrine of the earth's rotation. That his phraseology, however indirect, was perfectly understood by contemporary philosophers, both assentient and dissentient, as embodying his belief in the doctrine--is attested by the two passages of Aristotle. Upon these reasons alone I should dissent from M. Cousin's sixth argument. But I have other reasons besides. He rests it upon the two allegations that the doctrine of the earth's motion was the subject of much controversial debate in Plato's time, and of great importance in itself. Now the first of these two allegations can hardly be proved, as to the time of Plato; for Aristotle, when he is maintaining the earth's immobility, does not specify any other opponents than the Pythagoreians and the followers of the Platonic Timaeus. And the second allegation I believe to be unfounded, speaking with reference to the Platonic Timaeus. In the cosmical system therein embodied, the rotation of the earth round the cosmical axis, though a real part of the system, was in itself a fact of no importance, and determining no results. The capital fact of the system was the position and function of the earth, packed close round the centre of the cosmical axis, and regulating the revolutions of that axis. Plato had no motive to bring prominently forward the circumstance that the earth revolved itself along with the cosmical axis, which circumstance was only an incidental accompaniment. I have thus examined all the arguments adduced by M. Cousin, and have endeavoured to show that they fail in establishing his conclusion. There is, however, one point of the controversy in which I concur with him more than with Boeckh and Martin. This point is the proper conception of what Plato means by the _cosmical axis_. Boeckh and Martin seem to assume this upon the analogy of what is now spoken of as the axis of the earth: M. Boeckh (p. 13) declares the axis of the kosmos to be a prolongation of that axis. But it appears to me (and M. Cousin's language indicates the same) that Plato's conception was something very different. The axis of the earth (what astronomers speak of as such) is an imaginary line traversing the centre of the earth; a line round which the earth revolves. Now the cosmical axis, as Plato conceives it, is a solid material cylinder, which not only itself revolves, but causes by this revolution the revolution of the exterior circumference of the kosmos. This is a conception entirely different from that which we mean when we speak of the axis of the earth. It is, however, a conception symbolically enunciated in the tenth book of the Republic, where the spindle of Necessity is said to be composed of adamant, hard and solid material, and to cause by its own rotation the rotation of all the _verticilli_ packed and fastened around it. What is thus enunciated in the Republic is implied in the Timaeus. For when we read therein that the earth is packed or fastened round the cosmical axis, how can we understand it to be packed or fastened round an imaginary line? I will add that the very same meaning is brought out in the translation of Cicero--"_trajecto axe sustinetur_" (terra). The axis, round which the earth is fastened, and which sustains the earth, must be conceived, not as an imaginary line, but as a solid cylinder, itself revolving; while the earth, being fastened round it, revolves round and along with it. The axis, in the sense of an imaginary line, cannot be found in the conception of Plato. Those contemporaries of Plato and Aristotle, who all agreed in asserting the revolution of the celestial sphere, did not all agree in their idea of the force whereby such revolution was brought about. Some thought that the poles of the celestial sphere exercised a determining force: others symbolised the mythical Atlas, as an axis traversing the sphere from pole to pole and turning it round. (Aristotel. De Motu Animal. 3. p. 699 a. 15-30.) Aristotle himself advocated the theory of a _primum movens immobile_ acting upon the sphere from without the sphere. Even in the succeeding centuries, when astronomy was more developed, Aratus, Eratosthenes, and their commentators, differed in their way of conceiving the cosmical axis. Most of them considered it as solid: but of these, some thought it was stationary, with the sphere revolving round it--others that it revolved itself: again, among these latter, some believed that the revolutions of the axis determined those of the surrounding sphere--others, that the revolutions of the sphere caused those of the axis within it. Again, there were some physical philosophers who looked at the axis as airy or spiritual--[Greek: to\ dia\ me/sou te=s sphai/ras die=kon pneu=ma]. Then there were geometers who conceived it only as an imaginary line. (See the Phaenomena of Aratus 20-25--with the Scholia thereon; Achilles Tatius ad Arati Phaenom. apud Petavium--Uranolog. p. 88; also Hipparchus ad Arat. ib. p. 144.) I do not go into these dissentient opinions farther than to show, how indispensable it is, when we construe the passage in the Platonic Timaeus, [Greek: peri\ to\n dia\ panto\s po/lon tetame/non], to enquire in what sense Plato understood the cosmical axis: and how unsafe it is to assume at once that he must have conceived it as an imaginary line. Proklus argues that because the earth is mentioned by Plato in the Phaedon as stationary in the centre of the heaven, we cannot imagine Plato to affirm its rotation in the Timaeus. I agree with M. Boeckh in thinking this argument inconclusive; all the more, because, in the Phaedon, not a word is said either about the axis of the kosmos, or about the rotation of the kosmos; all that Sokrates professes to give is [Greek: te\n i)de/an te=s ge=s kai\ tou\s to/pous au)te=s**] (p. 108 E). No cosmical system or theory is propounded in that dialogue. When we turn to the Phaedrus, we find that, in its highly poetical description, the rotation of the heaven occupies a prominent place. The internal circumference of the heavenly sphere, as well as its external circumference or back ([Greek: no=ton]), are mentioned; also its periodical rotations, during which the gods are carried round on the back of the heaven, and contemplate the eternal Ideas occupying the super-celestial space (p. 247, 248), or the plain of truth.[5] But the purpose of this poetical representation appears to be metaphysical and intellectual, to illustrate the antithesis presented by the world of Ideas and Truth on one side--against that of sense and appearances on the other. Astronomically and cosmically considered, no intelligible meaning is conveyed. Nor can we even determine whether the rotations of the heaven, alluded to in the Phaedrus, are intended to be diurnal or not; I incline to believe not ([Greek: me/chri te=s _e(te/ras_ perio/dou]--p. 248--which can hardly be understood of so short a time as one day). Lastly, nothing is said in the Phaedrus about the cosmical axis; and it is upon this that the rotations of the earth intimated in the Timaeus depend. [Footnote 5: Whether [Greek: E)sti/a] in the Phaedrus, which is said "to remain alone stationary in the house of the Gods," can be held to mean the Earth, is considered by Proklus to be uncertain (p. 681).] Among the different illustrations, given by Plato in his different dialogues respecting the terrestrial and celestial bodies, I select the tenth book of the Republic as that which is most suitable for comparison with the Timaeus, because it is only therein that we learn how Plato conceived the axis of the kosmos. M. Boeckh (Untersuchungen, p. 86) wishes us to regard the difference between the view taken in the Phaedon, and that in the Republic, as no way important; he affirms that the adamantine spindle in the Republic is altogether mythical or poetical, and that Plato conceives the axis as not being material. On this point I dissent from M. Boeckh. The mythical illustrations in the tenth book of the Republic appear to me quite unsuitable to the theory of an imaginary, stationary, and immaterial axis. Here I much more agree with Gruppe (p. 15, 26-29), who recognises the solid material axis as an essential feature of the cosmical theory in the Republic; and recognises also the marked difference between that theory and what we read in the Phaedon. Yet, though Gruppe is aware of this important difference between the Republic and the Phaedon, he still wishes to illustrate the Timaeus by the latter and not by the former. He affirms that the earth in the Timaeus is conceived as unattached, and freely suspended, the same as in the Phaedon; but that in the Timaeus it is conceived, besides, as revolving on its own axis, which we do not find in the Phaedon (p. 28, 29). Here I think Gruppe is mistaken. In construing the words of Timaeus, [Greek: ei(lome/nen (i)llome/nen) peri\ to\n dia\ panto\s po/lon tetame/non], as designating "the unattached earth revolving round its own axis," he does violence not less to the text of Plato than to the expository comment of Aristotle. Neither in the one nor the other is anything said about _an axis of the earth_; in both, the cosmical axis is expressly designated; and, if Gruppe is right in his interpretation of [Greek: ei(lome/nen], we must take Plato as affirming, not that the earth is fastened round the cosmical axis, but that it revolves, though unattached, around that axis, which is a proposition both difficult to understand, and leading to none of those astronomical consequences with which Gruppe would connect it. Again, when Gruppe says that [Greek: ei(lome/nen peri\] does _not_ mean _packed or fastened round_, but that it _does_ mean _revolving round_, he has both the analogies of the word and the other commentators against him. The main proof, if not the only proof, which he brings, is that Aristotle so construed it. Upon this point I join issue with him. I maintain that Aristotle does _not_ understand [Greek: ei(lome/nen] or [Greek: i)llome/nen peri\] as naturally meaning _revolving round_, and that he does understand the phrase as meaning _fastened round_. When we find him, in the second passage of the treatise De Coelo, not satisfied with the verb [Greek: i)/llesthai] alone, but adding to it the second verb [Greek: _kai\ kinei=sthai_], we may be sure that he did not consider [Greek: i)/llesthai] as naturally and properly denoting _to revolve_ or _move round_. Agreeing as I do with Gruppe in his view, that the interpretation put by Aristotle is the best evidence which we can follow in determining the meaning of this passage in the Timaeus, I contend that the authority of Aristotle contradicts instead of justifying the conclusion at which he arrives. Aristotle understands [Greek: i)llome/nen] as meaning _packed or fastened round_; he does not understand it as meaning, when taken by itself, _revolving round_. The two meanings here indicated are undoubtedly distinct and independent. But they are not for that reason contradictory and incompatible. It has been the mistake of critics to conceive them as thus incompatible; so that if one of the two were admitted, the other must be rejected. I have endeavoured to show that this is not universally true, and that there are certain circumstances in which the two meanings not only may come together, but must come together. Such is the case when we revert to Plato's conception of the cosmical axis as a solid revolving cylinder. That which is packed or fastened around the cylinder must revolve around it, and along with it. Both M. Boeckh and Gruppe assume the incompatibility of the two meanings; and we find the same assumption in Plutarch's criticisms on the Timaeus (Plutarch. Quaest. Platon. p. 1006 C), where he discusses what Plato means by [Greek: o)/rgana chro/nou]; and in what sense the earth as well as the moon can be reckoned as [Greek: o)/rganon chro/nou] (Timaeus, p. 41 E, 42 D). Plutarch inquires how it is possible that the earth, if stationary and at rest, can be characterised as "among the instruments of time;" and he explains it by saying that this is true in the same sense as we call a gnomon or sun-dial an instrument of time, because, though itself never moves, it marks the successive movements of the shadow. This explanation might be admissible for the phrase [Greek: o)/rganon chro/nou]; but I cannot think that the immobility of the earth can be made compatible with the attribute which Plato bestows upon it of being [Greek: phu/lax kai\ _demiourgo\s_ nukto\s te kai\ e(me/ras]. The difficulty, however, vanishes when we understand the function ascribed by Plato to the earth as I have endeavoured to elucidate it. The earth not only is not at rest, but cannot be at rest, precisely because it is packed round the solid revolving cosmical axis, and must revolve along with it. The function of the earth, as the first and oldest of intra-kosmic deities, is to uphold and regulate the revolutions of this axis, upon which depend the revolutions of the sidereal sphere or outer shell of the kosmos. It is by virtue of this regulating function (and not by virtue of its rotation) that the earth is the guardian and artificer of night and day. It is not only "an instrument of time," but the most potent and commanding among all instruments of time. What has just been stated is, in my belief, the theory of the Platonic Timaeus, signified in the words of that dialogue, and embodied in the comment of Aristotle. The commentators, subsequent to Aristotle, so far as we know them, understood the theory in a sense different from what Plato intended. I think we may see how this misconception arose. It arose from the great development and elaboration of astronomical theory during the two or three generations immediately succeeding Plato. Much was added by Eudoxus and others, in their theory of concentric spheres: more still by others of whom we read in Cicero (Academ. II. 39.) "Hicetas Syracusius, ut ait Theophrastus, coelum, solem, lunam, stellas, supera denique omnia, stare censet, neque praeter terram rem ullam in mundo moveri: quae cum circum axem se summa celeritate convertat et torqueat, eadem effici omnia, quae si stante terra coelum moveretur. Atque hoc etiam Platonem in Timaeo dicere quidam arbitrantur, sed paullo obscurius." The same doctrine is said to have been held by Herakleides of Pontus, the contemporary of Aristotle, and by others along with him. (Simplikius ad Aristot. Physic. p. 64--De Coelo, p. 132--Plutarch. Plac. Phil. III. 13.) The doctrine of the rotation of the Earth here appears along with another doctrine--the immobility of the sidereal sphere and of the celestial bodies. The two are presented together, as correlative portions of one and the same astronomical theory. There are no celestial revolutions, and therefore there is no solid celestial axis. Moreover, even Aristarchus of Samos (who attained to a theory substantially the same as the Copernican, with the double movement of the Earth, rotation round its own axis, and translation round the sun as a centre) comes within less than a century after Plato's death. Though the _quidam_ alluded to by Cicero looked upon the obscure sentence in Plato's Timaeus as a dim indication of the theory of Hicetas, yet the two agree only in the supposition of a rotation of the earth, and differ essentially in the pervading cosmical conceptions. Hicetas states distinctly that which his theory denies, as well as that which it affirms. The negation of the celestial rotations, is in his theory a point of capital and coordinate importance, on which he contradicts both Plato and Aristotle as well as the apparent evidence of sense. I cannot suppose that this theory can have been proclaimed or known to Aristotle when his works were composed: for the celestial revolutions are the keystone of his system, and he could hardly have abstained from combating a doctrine which denied them altogether. In the hands of Hicetas (perhaps in those of Herakleides, if we may believe what is said about him) astronomy appears treated as a science by itself, with a view "to provide such hypotheses as may save the phenomena" ([Greek: so/zein ta\ phaino/mena], Simpl. ad Aristot. De Coelo, p. 498, Schol. Brandis). It becomes detached from those religious, ethical, poetical, teleological, arithmetical decrees or fancies, in which we see it immersed in the Platonic Timaeus, and even (though somewhat less) in the Aristotelian Treatise De Coelo. Hence the meaning of Plato, obscurely announced from the beginning, ceased to be understood: the solid revolving axis of the Kosmos, assumed without being expressly affirmed in his Timaeus, dropped out of sight: the doctrine of the rotation of the earth was presented in a new point of view, as a substitute for the celestial revolutions. But no proper note was taken of this transition. The doctrine of Plato was assumed to be the same as that of Hicetas. When we read Plutarch's criticism (Quaest. Plat. p. 1006 C) upon the word [Greek: i)llome/nen], we see that he puts to himself the question thus--"Does Plato in the Timaeus conceive the earth as kept together and stationary--or as turning round and revolving, agreeably to the subsequent theory of Aristarchus and Seleukus?" Here we find that Plutarch conceives the alternative thus--Either the earth does not revolve at all, or it revolves as Aristarchus understood it. One or other of these two positions must have been laid down by Plato in the Timaeus.--So we read in Plutarch. But the fact is, that Plato meant neither the one nor the other. The rotation of the earth round the solid cosmical axis, which he affirms in the Timaeus--is a phenomenon utterly different from the rotation of the earth as a free body round the imaginary line called its own axis, which was the doctrine of Aristarchus. When expositors in Plutarch's day, and since his day, enquired whether or not the Platonic Timaeus affirmed the rotation of the earth, they meant to designate the rotation of the earth in the sense of Aristarchus, and in the sense in which modern astronomy understands that capital fact. Now speaking the language of modern astronomy, I think it certain that the rotation of the earth is _not_ to be found affirmed in the Platonic Timaeus; and I agree with M. Boeckh when he says (Untersuch. p. 77), "Granting that Aristotle ascribed to Plato the doctrine of the rotation of the earth, he at least did not ascribe to him the doctrine as Gruppe assumes, and as now understood." As between Gruppe--who holds that the Platonic Timaeus affirms the rotation of the earth, and that Aristotle ascribes it to him, in our sense of the words--and M. Boeckh, who denies this--I stand with the latter for the negative. But when M. Boeckh assumes that the only alternative doctrine is the immobility of the earth, and tries to show that this doctrine is proclaimed in the Platonic Timaeus--nay, that no opposite doctrine _can_ be proclaimed, because the discourse expressly announces the rotation of the sidereal heaven in twenty-four hours--I am compelled to dissent from him as to the conclusion, and to deny the cogency of his proof. M. Boeckh has hardly asked himself the question, whether there was not some other sense in which Plato might have affirmed it in the Timaeus. I have endeavoured to show that there was another sense; that there are good analogies in Plato to justify the belief that he intended to affirm the doctrine in that other sense; and that the comments of Aristotle--while thoroughly pertinent, if we thus understand the passage in the Timaeus--become either irrelevant, dishonest, or absurd, if we construe the passage as signifying either what is maintained by M. Boeckh or what is maintained by Gruppe. The eminent critics, whose opinions I here controvert, have been apparently misled by the superior astronomical acquirements of the present age, and have too hastily made the intellectual exigencies of their own minds a standard for all other minds, in different ages as well as in different states of cultivation. The question before us is, not what doctrines are scientifically true or scientifically compatible with each other, but what doctrines were affirmed or implied by Plato. In interpreting him, we are required to keep our minds independent of subsequent astronomical theories. We must look, first and chiefly, to what is said by Plato himself; next, if that be obscure, to the construction and comments of his contemporaries so far as they are before us. In no case is this more essential than in the doctrine of the rotation of the earth, which in the modern mind has risen to its proper rank in scientific importance, and has become connected with collateral consequences and associations foreign to the ideas of the ancient Pythagoreans, or Plato, or Aristotle. Unless we disengage ourselves from these more recent associations, we cannot properly understand the doctrine as it stands in the Platonic Timaeus. This doctrine, as I have endeavoured to explain it, leads to an instructive contrast between the cosmical theories of Plato (in the Timaeus) and Aristotle. Plato conceives the kosmos as one animated and intelligent being or god, composed of body and soul. Its body is moved and governed by its soul, which is fixed or rooted in the centre, but stretches to the circumference on all sides, as well as all round the exterior. It has a perpetual movement of circular rotation in the same unchanged place, which is the sort of movement most worthy of a rational and intelligent being. The revolutions of the exterior or sidereal sphere (Circle of the Same) depend on and are determined by the revolutions of the solid cylinder or axis, which traverses the kosmos in its whole diameter. Besides these, there are various interior spheres or circles (Circles of the Different), which rotate by distinct and variable impulses in a direction opposite to the sidereal sphere. This latter is so much more powerful than they, that it carries them all round with it; yet they make good, to a certain extent, their own special opposite movement, which causes their positions to be ever changing, and the whole system to be complicated. But the grand capital, uniform, overpowering, movement of the kosmos, consists in the revolution of the solid axis, which determines that of the exterior sidereal sphere. The impulse or stimulus to this movement comes from the cosmical soul, which has its root in the centre. Just at this point is situated the earth, "the oldest and most venerable of intra-kosmic deities," packed round the centre of the axis, and having for its function to guard and regulate those revolutions of the axis, and through them those of the outer sphere, on which the succession of day and night depends--as well as to nurse mankind. In all this we see that the ruling principle and force of the kosmos ([Greek: to\ e(gemoniko\n tou= ko/smou]) is made to dwell in and emanate from _its centre_. When we come to Aristotle, we find that the ruling principle or force of the kosmos is placed, not in its centre, but in its circumference. He recognises no solid revolving axis traversing the whole diameter of the kosmos The interior of the kosmos is occupied by the four elements--earth, water, air, fire--neither of which can revolve except by violence or under the pressure of extraneous force. To each of them rectilinear motion is _natural_; earth moves naturally towards the centre--fire moves naturally towards the circumference, away from the centre. But the peripheral substance of the kosmos is radically distinct from the four elements: rotatory motion in a circle is _natural_ to it, and is the only variety of motion natural to it. That it is moved at all, it owes to a _primum movens immobile_ impelling it: but the two are coeternal, and the motion has neither beginning nor end. That when moved, its motion is rotatory and not rectilinear, it owes to its own nature. It rotates perpetually, through its own nature and inherent virtue, not by constraining pressure communicated from a centre or from a soul. If constraint were required--if there were any contrary tendency to be overcome--the revolving periphery would become fatigued, and would require periods of repose; but, since in revolving it only obeys its own peculiar nature, it persists for ever without knowing fatigue. This peripheral or fifth essence, perpetually revolving, is the divine, venerable, and commanding portion of the kosmos, more grand and honourable than the interior parts or the centre. Aristotle lays this down (De Coelo, ii. 13, p. 293, b. 10) in express antithesis to the Pythagoreans, who (like Plato) considered the centre as the point of grandeur and command, placing fire in the centre for that reason. The earth has no positive cosmical function in Aristotle; it occupies the centre because all its parts have a natural movement towards the centre: and it is unmoved because there _must be_ something in the centre which is always stationary, as a contrary or antithesis to the fifth essence or peripheral substance of the kosmos, which is in perpetual rotation by its own immutable nature. I do not here go farther into the exposition of these ancient cosmical theories. I have adverted to Aristotle's doctrine only so far as was necessary to elucidate, by contrast, that which I believe to be the meaning of the Platonic Timaeus about the rotation of the earth. LONDON: PRINTED BY W. CLOWES AND SONS, STAMFORD STREET, AND CHARING CROSS. **************************************************************** Transcriber's Note The text is based on versions made available by the Internet Archive. For the Greek transcriptions the following conventions have been used: ) is for smooth breathing; ( for hard; + for diaeresis; / for acute accent; \ for grave; = for circumflex; | for iota subscript. ch is used for chi, ph for phi, ps for psi, th for theta; e for eta and o for omega; u is used for upsilon in all cases. Corrections to the text, indicated with ** Text Correction Ti/ma/io Ti/maio chore/ia chorei/a ou)/ranon ou)rano\n tetamenon tetame/non e)ndeiknutai e)ndei/knutai] forge force Tima/io| Timai/o| gegraptai ge/graptai] e(ilei=sthai ei(lei=sthai e)/pi\ e)pi\ a)ute=s au)te=s End of the Project Gutenberg EBook of Plato's Doctrine respecting the rotation of the Earth and Aristotle's Comment upon that Doctrine, by George Grote *** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK PLATO'S DOCTRINE--ROTATION OF EARTH *** ***** This file should be named 40439.txt or 40439.zip ***** This and all associated files of various formats will be found in: http://www.gutenberg.org/4/0/4/3/40439/ Produced by Ed Brandon as part of the on-line Grote Project Updated editions will replace the previous one--the old editions will be renamed. Creating the works from public domain print editions means that no one owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without permission and without paying copyright royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to copying and distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm concept and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if you charge for the eBooks, unless you receive specific permission. If you do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the rules is very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and research. They may be modified and printed and given away--you may do practically ANYTHING with public domain eBooks. Redistribution is subject to the trademark license, especially commercial redistribution. *** START: FULL LICENSE *** THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK To protect the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting the free distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work (or any other work associated in any way with the phrase "Project Gutenberg"), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full Project Gutenberg-tm License available with this file or online at www.gutenberg.org/license. Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works 1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property (trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in your possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work and you do not agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8. 1.B. "Project Gutenberg" is a registered trademark. It may only be used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works if you follow the terms of this agreement and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below. 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the Foundation" or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Nearly all the individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the United States. If an individual work is in the public domain in the United States and you are located in the United States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on the work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting free access to electronic works by freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm works in compliance with the terms of this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg-tm name associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms of this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with its attached full Project Gutenberg-tm License when you share it without charge with others. 1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying, performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this work or any other Project Gutenberg-tm work. The Foundation makes no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in any country outside the United States. 1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg: 1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work on which the phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the phrase "Project Gutenberg" is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or distributed: This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org 1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is derived from the public domain (does not contain a notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the copyright holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in the United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase "Project Gutenberg" associated with or appearing on the work, you must comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9. 1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is posted with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms will be linked to the Project Gutenberg-tm License for all works posted with the permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of this work. 1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg-tm License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg-tm. 1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project Gutenberg-tm License. 1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary, compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format other than "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site (www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other form. Any alternate format must include the full Project Gutenberg-tm License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1. 1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying, performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg-tm works unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9. 1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing access to or distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works provided that - You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, "Information about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation." - You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project Gutenberg-tm works. - You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days of receipt of the work. - You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works. 1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from both the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and Michael Hart, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark. Contact the Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below. 1.F. 1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread public domain works in creating the Project Gutenberg-tm collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may contain "Defects," such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or cannot be read by your equipment. 1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the "Right of Replacement or Refund" described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, and any other party distributing a Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE. 1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium with your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you with the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received the work electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose to give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing without further opportunities to fix the problem. 1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS', WITH NO OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE. 1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages. If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions. 1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the production, promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works, harmless from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees, that arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg-tm work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any Defect you cause. Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg-tm Project Gutenberg-tm is synonymous with the free distribution of electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations from people in all walks of life. Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg-tm's goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg-tm collection will remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure and permanent future for Project Gutenberg-tm and future generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at www.gutenberg.org Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal Revenue Service. The Foundation's EIN or federal tax identification number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state's laws. The Foundation's principal office is located at 4557 Melan Dr. S. Fairbanks, AK, 99712., but its volunteers and employees are scattered throughout numerous locations. Its business office is located at 809 North 1500 West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up to date contact information can be found at the Foundation's web site and official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact For additional contact information: Dr. Gregory B. Newby Chief Executive and Director gbnewby@pglaf.org Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation Project Gutenberg-tm depends upon and cannot survive without wide spread public support and donations to carry out its mission of increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be freely distributed in machine readable form accessible by the widest array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt status with the IRS. The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any particular state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who approach us with offers to donate. International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff. Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project Gutenberg-tm concept of a library of electronic works that could be freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and distributed Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks with only a loose network of volunteer support. Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks are often created from several printed editions, all of which are confirmed as Public Domain in the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper edition. Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search facility: www.gutenberg.org This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg-tm, including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.